Ron
Davis is a young California artist whose new paintings, recently
shown
at the Tibor de Nagy Gallery in New York, are among the most significant
produced anywhere during the past few years, and place him, along
with Stella and Bannard, at the forefront of his generation. In
at
least two respects Davis' work is characteristically Californian:
it makes impressive use of new materials specifically, plastic
backed with fiberglass and it exploits an untrammeled illusionism.
But these previously had yielded nothing more than extraordinarily
attractive objects, such as Larry Bell's coated glass boxes, or ravishing,
ostensibly pictorial effects, as in Robert Irwin's recent work. (In
the first instance illusion is rendered literal, while in the second
it dissolves literalness entirely.) Whereas Davis' new work achieves
an unequivocal identity as painting. That this is so is a matter of
conviction. One recognizes Davis' new work as painting: in my case,
with amazement and, at first, distrust, even resentment
that what I was experiencing as paintings were, after all, made of
plastic. Not that Davis' paintings are what they are in spite of being
made of plastic or presenting a compelling illusion of a solid object
in strong perspective. On the contrary, it is precisely Davis' refusal
to settle for anything but ambitious painting that, one feels, has
compelled him to use both new materials and two-point perspective.
What incites amazement is that that ambition could be realized in
this way that, for example, after a lapse of at least a century,
rigorous perspective could again be come a medium of painting.
Davis'
paintings are, I suggest, the most extreme response so far to the
situation described in my essay Shape as Form: Frank Stella's New
Paintings.1 Roughly, Davis has used perspective illusion the illusion that the painting as a whole is a solid object
seen in two-point perspective from above to relieve the pressure
under which, within that situation, the shape of the support (or
literal
shape) has come to find itself. The limits of Davis' new paintings
present themselves as the edges of a three-dimensional entity rather
than of a flat surface; and in fact it is virtually impossible to
grasp the literal shape of paintings like Six-Ninths Blue and
Six-Ninths Red just by looking at them. (One is forced, so
to speak, to trace their limits and then see what one has.) As a
result,
the question of whether or not the literal shapes of Davis' new paintings
hold, or stamp them selves out, or compel conviction a burning question
within the situation referred to simply does not arise. More
precisely, it does not arise as long as the illusion of three dimensionality
remains compelling: if, in a given painting, for whatever reason;
the illusion is felt to be in jeopardy, that painting's ability to
hold as shape is rendered question able as well. (Something of the
kind may happen in Two-Ninths Grey, in which the projected
object is not, to my mind, sufficiently comprehensible. What, for
example, is the precise relation of the two gray blocks to the larger
red slab on which they seem to sit? In general, Davis cannot afford
much ambiguity or indeterminacy, both of which compromise his paintings'
apparent objecthood.)2 |
A
great deal, then, depends upon the power of the illusion; and it
was,
I believe, in order to achieve that power that Davis gave up working
in paint on canvas and began to explore the possibility of making
his new paintings in plastic. In any case, the fact that in his
new
paintings color is not applied to the surface in any way, but instead
seems physically to lie somewhere behind it, makes the illusion
of
objecthood infinitely more compelling than would otherwise be the
case. In this respect Davis' new paintings represent not only an
inspired
resuscitation of, but a deep break with, traditional illusionism:
in the latter paint on the surface of the canvas creates the illusion
of objects in space; while in Davis' paintings whatever makes the
illusion is not, it seems, situated on, or at, the surface at all.
(The illusion of objecthood is intensified still more by the way
in
which the colored plastic in which Davis has also mixed mirror
flake, aluminum powder, bronze powder and pearl essence not
merely represents but imitates the materiality of solid things.) Conversely,
the surface of these paintings is experienced in unique isolation
from the illusion. It has been prized loose from the rest of the painting
- as though what hangs on the wall is the surface alone. In Davis'
new paintings a detached surface coexists with a detached illusion.
(In this respect his paintings are the opposite of Olitski's, in which
there is "an illusion of depth that somehow extrudes all suggestions
of depth back to the picture's surface."3) Indeed, the
detached surface coincides with the detached illusion: which is why
the question of whether or not the shape of that surface holds or
stamps itself out does not arise. Davis deliberately and, I
think, profoundly heightens one's sense of the mutual independence
of surface and illusion by rather sharply beveling the edges of his
paintings from behind. This means that even when the beholder is not
standing directly in front of a given painting, no support of any
kind can be seen. The surface is felt to be exactly that, a surface,
and nothing more. It is not, one might say, the surface of anything
except, of course, of a painting.
Moreover,
Davis' surface is something new in painting: not because it is shiny
and reflects light that was also true of the varnished surfaces
of the Old Masters but be cause what one experiences as surface
in these paintings is that reflectance and nothing more. The precise
degree of reflectance is important. If the painting is too shiny the
surface is emphasized at the expense of the illusion; and this in
turn under mines the independence of both. At the same time, Davis'
paintings make transparency important as never be fore: not because
their surfaces are experienced as transparent one does not,
I want to say, look through so much as past them4 but
because the layers of colored plastic behind their surfaces vary
in opacity. The relation between the surface and the rest of a transparent
object is different from that between the surface and the rest of
an opaque one: roughly, in the former case it is as though the beholder
can see all of the object, not just the portion that his eyesight
touches. In Davis' new work this difference becomes important to
painting
for the first time, by making possible, or greatly strengthening,
the relation between surface and illusion that I have tried to describe.
Finally,
I want at least to touch on the character of the illusionism in these
paintings. Despite its dependence on the rigorous application of
two-point
perspective, it, too, is new in painting. Roughly, the illusion is
of something one takes to be a square slab (some portions of which
have been removed), turned so that one of its corners points in the
general direction of the beholder, and seen from above. What seems
to me of special interest is this: the illusion is such that one
simply
assumes that the projected slab is horizontal, as though Laying on
the ground; but this means that looking down at it could be managed
only from a position considerably above both the slab itself and
the
imaginary ground-plane it seems to define. Moreover, the beholder
is not only suspended above the slab; he is simultaneously tilted
toward it otherwise he would not be in a position to look
down at the slab at all. In Davis' new paintings the illusion of
objecthood
does not excavate the wall so much as it dissolves the ground under
one's feet: as though experiencing the surface and the illusion independently
of one another were the result of standing in radically different
physical relations to them. Davis' illusionism addresses itself not
just to eyesight but to a sense that might be called one of directionality.
There have been strong intimations of such a development in recent
painting, notably that of Noland and Olitski; in fact, I recently
claimed of Olitski's spray paintings that what is appealed to is
not
our ability in locating objects (or failing to) but in orienting
ourselves (or failing to).5 This seems to me dramatically true of
Davis' new paintings as well.
The
possibilities which Davis has been able to realize in his first plastic
paintings still seem to me scarcely imaginable. The possibilities
which they open up belong to the future of painting.
1. ARTFORUM Vol. 5, No. 3, November 1966 (reprinted in Art
and Objecthood, 1998).
2. At
the moment I wrote this article, I had evidently not yet arrived
at the argument of "Art and Objecthood" (reprinted in Art and Objecthood, 1998);
had I done so, I probably would have found a way to characterize
Davis' paintings other than in
terms of an illusion of "objecthood," a loaded notion
in the essay I was soon to begin. M.F., 1996
3. Clement Greenberg, "Introduction to Jules Olitski at the
1966 Venice Biennial." in Modernism with a Vengeance 19571969,
vol. 4 of The Collected Essays and Criticism, ed. John O'Brian
(Chicago, 1993. p. 230).
4. Not the way one looks past an object so much as the way one
looks past a reflection.
5. In the catalog essay to Olitski's exhibition (reprinted in Art
and Objecthood, 1998) at the Corcoran Gallery.
|