There
was a lot of painting done in the sixties. No review could describe
and evaluate all of it and it is unlikely that any art writer would
want to try. The first thing to do is to select the work, and usually
we play the part of history, try to pick out, at a short distance in
time, art of high quality, art which will last. Give or take a few
lapses, "history" is the most convincing critic, and most
art writers try to stand by her side. But how does one know what is
good of recent art? If you put it straight to them most members of
the art public would quickly answer that there is no sure clue or giveaway.
Outlines and systems for art quality crumble as the changing tides
wash them away. The only "sure thing" is a good eye. But
most art writers do not have a good eye, as any history of art criticism
will reveal, and they cast about for the very clues to art quality
they would be the first to admit do not exist.
Everyone
of the art public has a bank of assimilated taste consisting of fairly
recent good art which he has been able to digest, against which he
judges the new art he comes up against. He applied the lessons learned
from art which has stood up to 10, 20, or 50 years of history to the
art of right now. The present generation of critics, museum directors,
and the lot, endowed with a strong sense of history and a determination
not to be "wrong," have been clever enough to take in not
only the successes of recent art, but also the failures of past criticism
as a negative guide to assure that they do not pick against history.
They live with the scepter of the critic who denounced new art which
proved to be important, and these are the key words of the sixties,
the all-purpose catch phrase of the eyeless art public: new and
important.
History
has told us that good art looks new, except for a family resemblance
to the art it "outdates," and that it influences artists.
This gives rise to trends and full-fledged art-making styles. We have
learned our lesson well, and now, as we say good-bye to the sixties,
we see newness and importance securely fixed as safe taste. But the
use of clues and signs always catches up to those who will not see
art properly. The mediocre ambitious artist is always a few jumps ahead;
he has a keen nose for "what's in the air" and he wastes
no time bringing it into his art. It is still true that good art is
new and important. What is unique to the sixties is that bad art is
now new and important. As always, bad art takes aim at assimilated
taste. But it has taken until now for assimilated taste to demand these
qualities. This has produced something else peculiar to the sixties:
the coexistence of many very different-looking styles of art-making,
each claiming to be as much "high art" as the others, each
with its defenders and detractors. It was not like that in the fifties.
There were a few individualists then as now, but Abstract Expressionism
was a mammoth tidal wave unlike anything we have today. These recent
coexisting styles are symptomatic of the demand for newness and importance;
to be new is to be different and to be important is to be generative therefore,
many styles going along parallel lines in time. The fear of being "wrong" fosters
acceptance of bad art as long as the art public is not sure it is actually
bad. History has told them to go along with whatever seems to persist.
And their own indecision sustains the very persistence they seek. And
so we have the spectacle of mighty art institutions like the Museum
of Modern Art loaded to the hatches with chichi junk, like Marisol
sculpture, hideous Wesselmann paintings, the grim idiocy of Lucas Samaras,
all kinds of bobbling, clicking, flashing and wiggling things, and
exhibitions of photographs of gigantic earth and sky "works" which
are as destructive as they are silly. Everything has its place in this
hysterical anarchy. And now, just as 10, 50 or 100 years ago, 99 percent
of it is worthless. Only the superficial modes of selection have changed.
It
is not possible to rightly condemn a style of art-making, just as it
is not possible to rightly condemn any material for art, because it
cannot be shown that a good work of art will not come up in that style.
Conversely, there is no style which guarantees good art, though there
have been some, like Cubism and Impressionism and perhaps Fauvism,
which at the temporal center of their effective lifetimes have allowed
rather mediocre artists to paint very good paintings. But it is possible
to look back on a style and say that not much has come out of it. In
my experience, from what I have seen of the art of the last ten years,
the styles of Pop and "hard core" Minimal have produced nothing of
sufficient quality to pass the test of time. There are works that are
amusing, interesting, puzzling, works that have been influential and
have inspired discussions, but nothing really good.*
I
do think that all the really good painting of the past ten years has
a direct and specific link to the great art of the recent past, will
in time look much less discontinuous than it does now, and is related
more by a basic sameness of process and intent than by evident visual
similarity. The most striking characteristic of the best paintings
of the sixties, the factor of design which will let the art historian
of the future pinpoint a work of the sixties, is the extreme spatial
manipulation of the shape of the painting or of the elements of the
picture surface to give color a visually plausible place on the two-dimensional
abstract picture plane. Furthermore, with the exception of some painters
who persist in previous styles, I am of the opinion that all the
best painting of the sixties has been made by artists who have done
this.
The
two fundamental problems the serious abstract painter faces are those
of edge and isolation; the edge must be accommodated by design because
it is the strongest single factor of design of the surface, and the
elements of the surface tend to become isolated across the resistant
flatness of two dimensions. Realist painting has it easier than abstract
painting, and the Impressionists had it the best. Every illusion, every
color, every brush stroke was fully and naturally rationalized by the
character of their style. It seems that all of their problems were
solved before they started painting. The problem of relating bits of
colored paint across a closed-up flat surface was solved by the illusion
of realist depth, which allows the pieces to "reach" each
other across the apparent void; the problem of the edge, the strongest
element of design of a painting, was solved by the naturally-occurring
elements of landscapehorizons, trees, waterlines, bridges, housesall
of which reflect the edge and bring it into the painting; the problem
of ordering a vast and subtle variation of colors was solved by the
strict adherence to what was "seen"; the problem of the subjection
of paint to the service of imitation of materials not "natural" to
paint was solved by making the paintings actually consist of separate
touches of paint distinctly enough to stand as paint, though they made
up an illusion of another thing. Furthermore, Impressionism may have
been the only painting style to fuse the usually antagonistic approaches
to art-making: constructive painting, built up from the inside, and "effect" painting,
in which the paint is worked to achieve something preconceived. Impressionism
gave its practitioners a firmer, stronger base for painting than any
style before or since.
The
great continuing problem of abstract painting has been to build a basis
for painting as strong as that of Impressionism without the illusion
of reality.**
Cubism
got painting into abstraction by using the Impressionist stroke to
hack away at depicted subjects until the subjects were submerged under
the varied inflections of relief with vestiges of the subject functioning
decoratively. For reasons which I gave in detail in "Hofmann's
Rectangles" (Artforum, Summer, 1969), color was necessarily
excluded from this process. When color came back to Cubist painting,
in the teens, it was no longer the affective color of the Impressionists
and the Fauves, but a color at the service of space, color which served
to identify planes and distinguish areas. Thus it was that our first
powerful abstract style sacrificed one of the natural elements of painting
(color) for an element it had to fake (illusion in space). With a few
great exceptions like Matisse, that is the way it has been ever since,
or perhaps it is more accurate to say that Cubism, free of affective
color, has been far and away the most dominant style.
Color has been forced to work itself back into the "mainstream" of
painting by innovation.
Before
I describe some of those innovations there are two questions which
wait to be answered. First, why must there be affective color in painting,
and second, why is it such an accomplishment to get this color into
abstract painting?
Before
I describe some of those innovations there are two questions which
wait to be answered. First, why must there be affective color in painting,
and second, why is it such an accomplishment to get this color into
abstract painting?
The
answer to the second question must be more complex. It is twofold,
part psychological and part mechanical. (Again I am obliged to say
that it has been treated in greater detail in my previous essays for
this magazine, particularly in "Hofmann's Rectangles.") The
best and most serious artists of any era inherit the results of the
thinking of the best and most serious artists of previous eras. The
trenchant authority of the Cubist style has been immense. No high-minded
artist of the past 50 years has started out and matured without coming
to terms with Cubism. Some, like Rothko, Newman and Still, found their
own way around it, and some day it may be seen that they carried high
art through Abstract Expressionism. But the evident "mainstream," the
great wave of accepted art, the expanded Cubism which
is typified by the painting of de Kooning, came down on the maturing,
serious artist of 1960 like the proverbial ton of bricks. The most
sensitive and ambitious of them knew something was wrong, but artists
are only human, and it took a lot of nerve to turn against a style
so much in power. It seemed as though every step of art-making had
to be referred back to the canons of Abstract Expressionism for approval;
if not, it was necessary to take another stand, more violent and rebellious:
to accommodate Cubism with illustration (Rauschenberg), to mock Cubism
on its own terms by arranging the interior strictly in
terms of its edge (Stella) or to go to post-Cubist symmetry to open
up space for color (Noland). The only artist of the sixties to convert Cubism
into color painting and make great art of it was Hofmann. Some of the
reason for the eventual "takeover" of expressive color may
be that it is a positive, evolutionary way to break the yoke of Cubism;
certainly the erosion of Cubist picture-making by floods of color is
a most interesting process of the painting of the sixties. If it is
understood what an emotional burden Cubism-Abstract-Expressionism was
to the budding artist of the early sixties, we can move over to the
mechanical problems intrinsic to abstract color painting.
Most
of the apparently best artists accept abstraction for their art. Despite
the considerable advantages of realism they assume it is better to
loosen up the natural materials of paint and let them find their place.
From a practical standpoint abstract painting must be relational. If
a painted surface presents any set of inflections, and is shown as
art, it must be relational as long as we are directed to find art there,
because whatever art it has must arise from our consideration of the
variations on that surface. A non-relational painting, if such a thing
is possible, would have to be unsuitable for the medium of canvas.
This is why Minimal art finds its natural expression as sculpture.
There are other reasons why extremely simple art is usually also expressively
limited, limited as art, but they are philosophical in nature and too
demanding for this space.
If
successful abstract painting is more-or-less relational, as is indeed
the case, then the parts of the painting should relate,
and the few obstacles the better. This may not be necessarily true,
but I take it to be self-evident. It has certainly been true in my
experience as a painter and as a close observer of painting. All of
the essays to which I have been referring work around this principle,
and all of the recent painting which I feel is great painting has a
solidly constructed contrivance to freely relate the areas of the painted
surface. If a painting is done in terms of color, that surface must
be set up to allow the chosen colors to relate to each other as freely
and variously as possible. The first problem is that the flat surface
to be painted naturally impedes the relationship of the "pieces" placed
on it; these pieces have a hard time "reaching" each other
because anything else on that surface gets in the way. It is a problem
of topology, the mathematics of surface, known as the "map problem." No
more than four specific color areas can butt up together so that each
share some border with another. If another color is added it automatically
renders one or more of the colors to some degree remote. This gives
away the built-in difficulty of relating colored areas on a two-dimensional
surface. It is not the only problem facing the abstract painter but
it is primary.
The
means for relating elements of a painting done in spatial terms are
fairly clear to us at this time because they have been worked out in
painting, most dramatically by Pollock in his paintings of 1948 to
1952. I described this in Cubism, Abstract Expressionism, David
Smith (originally titled, Cubism, Pollock and Smith),
and I won't go into it here. Pollock did not do much with color because
his aims in art excluded color just as Cubism did, although not in
the same way. His paintings were made up of lines. Color is a fixed
feature of surface. To be usefully visible color must spread out, and
in spreading will cover surface. The more a painting done in terms
of color goes toward a rich variety of color, which is usually the
way it happens, the more the surface will be covered and the more the
colors will impinge on each other. The result is many mutually isolated
colored areas with little or no openness back to the canvas. The edge
is a special problem because it is the strongest factor of design of
the flat surface. If it is ignored a number of problems arise, according
to the style of the painting. One of two things usually happens; either
the edges cut off distinct forms which are not similar to the edge,
which evokes a feeling of arbitrary design, or a painting of fairly
uniform surface with not much light-dark variation turns into an object,
forcing visual consideration out of the painting. Any dispersal of
colors on a flat surface must make up for these things before it can
get started as a painting. All of the "color painters" of
the sixties have had to face these problems and beat them. There are
a number of ways to do this; the rest of this essay will describe a
few of the most inspired solutions as they have appeared in the painting
of the last ten years.
|